In a significant revision of his earlier article "The Objective Consciousness," Robert Heyward explores the fundamental foundations of consciousness and the primal duality of subject and object.


Any answers to the “hard problem” of consciousness will need to satisfy two distinct and differing lines of inquiry. Firstly they must align coherently with our scientific understanding of the universe, and secondly they must answer those questions which arise from the subjective experience consciousness brings to each individual. The physical sciences still offer no satisfactory answer to consciousness upon either front, while a plethora of mostly irrational metaphysical notions remain for the moment the only source of any wisdom on the matter.

Obviously, any metaphysic we do use to approach an answer must be freed of superstition, yet superstitious alternatives to scientific answers remain as ubiquitous and counterproductive as ever. Projected numena and qualia generally contaminate all metaphysical constructs, and this has ever resulted in the positing of metaphysical entities whose essential nature is not coherent with the known laws of the universe or, at least, that part of it which we know as “reality”. This is not to say that consciousness might not arise from an entity  or function of  whose existential nature we are currently unaware, but that any such entity must - by the fundamental ground of its sheer existence - share the properties of all known things and be thus in some part “knowable” through its continuance with all being.  As in all cases, the question is: “at what point do all things share an essential nature?”

Physical science insists that all things share the primal physical nature of the universe, that they all came from the mysterious original atom which somehow became unstable, and by exploding into time created the energetic laws of the universe and the primal particles from which all things have descended. Sounds a little familiar, doesn’t it? But the scientific-materialist take on the universal creation myth is a little narrow, to say the least. Thus the “hardness” of what it calls the “hard problem of consciousness” results - as an artifact of its own limited and essentially subjective outlook: in which only those entities whose properties are measurable are considered “objective”. Even a particularly stubborn materialist, however, will assert that the sky is blue, and that “blue” is indeed an object within his consciousness to which he is subject every time he looks at a clear sky. “So – exactly what is ‘blue’?” you ask him. “Hmm…,” he replies. “Now that’s a hard problem.”
 
Both scientists and scientific philosophers have been arguing over the right way to approach the hard problem for some time. One of the foremost of these thinkers is Professor David Chalmers of the Australian National University, and I quote here from his paper, “Moving Forward on the Problem of Consciousness”:

A further set of issues is raised by my appeal to fundamental laws in a theory of consciousness. Mills thinks that because I invoke such laws to bridge physics and consciousness, I am not really solving the hard problem at all (Price suggests something similar). At best I am providing a sophisticated set of correlations, and finding such correlations was an easy problem all along.

Mills reaches this conclusion because he construes the hard problem as the problem of giving a constitutive (or "non-causal") explanation of consciousness in physical terms. If the problem is construed that way, Mills is quite right that it is not being solved at all. But to define the problem of consciousness this way would be to define it so that it becomes unsolvable: one might call that problem the "impossible problem".

I prefer to set up the hard problem in such a way that a solution is not defined out of existence. The hard problem, as I understand it, is that of explaining how and why consciousness arises from physical processes in the brain. And I would argue the sort of theory I advocate can in principle offer a good solution to this problem. It will not solve the impossible problem of providing a reductive explanation of consciousness, but it will nevertheless provide a theory of consciousness that goes beyond correlation to explanation.”  (Quoted with permission of the author)

Whilst Chalmers here limits the hard problem by the recognition that experiential states of consciousness certainly exist but must be somehow subjective to an explanatory physical modality, my contention is that if we are to truly understand the apparently objective nature of consciousness as experience, then it is indeed the “impossible problem” with which we ultimately have to deal. Current scientific thinking continues within the assumption that consciousness arises within a purely physical state limited by the terms we currently accept as “physical law”. Thus the scientific materialist, by the very limits he seeks to extend, limits his own investigative field and makes his own “hard problem”. For indeed, while it might be acceptable to suggest that educated or adapted consciousness only and always arises at a certain level of organizational complexity, and thence to infer the laws governing the rise of such a conditional consciousness, this in itself does not in any way approach the real problem of “whence consciousness?” Chalmers argues that we might have to accept a pre-existing and indefinable fundamental law of nature which co-operates with physical laws to create what we know as physical awareness or the conditional consciousness of the brain. In this way the hard problem is averted by the a-priori acceptance of a metaphysical absolute. Now whilst this may be the only way of approaching the problem from the external, scientific viewpoint, even thinkers like Chalmers leave the explanation of the metaphysic off the agenda. Like magnetism or gravity, it just “is”, and is thus placed in the unanswered basket with all other supposedly “fundamental” forces of nature.
Physical science has no option but to step around the hard problem in this manner, for whilst at a deeper level it can be seen that it is created by a primal limit to human understanding, for materialistic science it is merely the logical impasse that results when one sets the laws one does understand as arbitrary limits to a system whose essential nature has yet to be discovered. To do any more than this, it becomes necessary to see how the interposition of conscious functions moulds not only our world view, but also the apparent laws we discover within it; to understand that our scientifically “objective” view of the cosmos is in fact seriously flawed - the subjective result of our maintaining the deeply ingrained bias that “seeing is believing” whilst living in a universe that clearly defies such “commonsense”. Wherever we look, at the edges of our understanding we now find ourselves ringed by the paradoxes created by this viewpoint and the explanatory fantasies we build in our attempts to step around them.

Nowhere is this more visible than in quantum physics, where the extraordinary behaviors of sub atomic particles are regarded not as the paradoxical artifacts of an incomplete view of the universe, but the essential realities of a mysterious and, at its microscopic limits, irrational and intractable natural world.
The strange and ineffably twisted geometry of relativistic space/time too, presents more as a paradox created by wrong thinking than a worthy description of a logically framed reality. Yet we are expected to accept such paradoxes as part of the natural order: that whilst all things macroscopic remain true to our sense of logic and geometrical reason, at some certain fineness of description they dissolve into irrationality.

Physicists seem to be able to step quietly about the paradoxes of relativity and quantum physics without scarcely a furtive glance while they weave ever more fantastic theories to explain them, yet confronted with the paradox of self awareness in a physical system they take a different line, asserting that no real paradox exists: that understanding consciousness is simply a matter of figuring out how the brain works; that the “hard problem” exists only though lack of data.

The truth is that the hard problem is just as hard as giving a clear, geometrically reasoned answer to how the apparently finite speed of light can be measurably the same in any reference frame. The fact that this is indeed the way the behavior of light appears subjectively to us, and that you can work a calculation to make things all add up ok in the end doesn’t wash away the underlying logical paradox, any more than does the answer that consciousness simply “happens” in complex systems and that understanding self awareness is just a matter of completely describing the system in which it occurs.

The materialistic philosophy which pervades current scientific thinking in regard to the brain sees consciousness only as a process; a process which relies for its existence on nothing else but a suitable arrangement of functional parts. Moreover, that none of these parts in themselves need have a particular specificity for consciousness – to the point where it is generally accepted that if all the functioning parts of the human brain could be replaced with electronic circuits, no essential difference would or could be determined between the operation of the living brain and its electronic counterpart. Such are the “commonsense” notions which flow from seeing consciousness as an epiphenomenon within an essentially “physical” universe.

More enlightened thinkers such as Chalmers reject this notion, yet rely for their approach on the acceptance that willy-nilly, self awareness must be the product of a fundamental condition ultimately reducible to physical laws.

The problem with such formulations is that they clearly avoid any and all of the evidence indicating that consciousness cannot be only an epiphenomenon; that the paradoxes and discontinuities within our apparently material universe not only offer direct evidence for its phenomenally objective nature as a fundamental universal dynamic not definable by consciously apprehended physical laws, but also offer ways to envision this dynamic and its correlations to experiential “self awareness”.

In a previous paper, (Relativity Revisited – 1997), I showed how the light speed paradox arises as a subjective artifact of conscious objectivity; that consciousness must exist as a functional part of the universe and not merely as a subjective counterpoint within some magically created, self aware limbo of brain process; that it must, in physical terms, participate spatially within the material universe.

Whilst it was satisfying to come even this far on the quest for an answer, my ideas still offered little access to the real problem itself, i.e. that of “whence consciousness
To discover more about this, it is necessary to revisit below some of our most basic ideas about the universe, and understand the essential nature of these as conscious notions.

Whilst the interests of science in this problem are obvious, the universe of discourse which shapes its investigations creates a limiting factor which precludes science as practiced, i.e., through a series of specialized and narrow endeavors, from seeing the true breadth of the problems conscious subjectivity creates even within its own postulations. For this reason alone, it is highly unlikely that scientific endeavor will ever reach an answer to the “hard problem” without encapsulating it within an already subjectively flawed view of reality. This is already seen through the attempts by mathematicians and physicists to posit conscious functionality and its relationship to lineal time via the activity of quantum effects in brain tissue - a process which seems to be little more than a mirroring back into the unknown of an already subjective take on another unknown. Such attempts merely illustrate how conscious subjectivity mediates the percepts and concepts of science at a deeper level than that at which it currently allows in its view of the universe.
 
Our personal need, however, is to know the answer to our own peculiar and individual awareness, and the meaning, if any, that it might have within the seemingly aloof and hostile universe in which we find ourselves - where our life-long struggle for survival only ends in the mystery of death and the apparent annihilation of all that we are and all that we have been.

Impersonal science has no problem with the notion that we are just mortal, chemical creatures: the accidental artifacts of a set of purely functional and arbitrary natural laws pertaining within an essentially fortuitous and meaningless universe. But personally we do have a problem with such an idea, a serious and inescapable problem. For, whilst we might agree that science has outlined the facts as they seem, we know deeply and intuitively that within no such arbitrary and essentially meaningless universe could our most extraordinary qualities of experience arise simply as after effects; as nothing more than a kind of meaningless gloss upon an otherwise pristine and purely mechanical functionality.

Thus the quest for understanding is essentially a personal quest, even if we should cloak it with the appearance of disinterested scientific inquiry. Being individuals, our lives are the only grist we have, our experiences the only “real” phenomena we can truly bring to the mill of our reason without their subordination to a collectively held, external philosophic position. And whilst it might be incumbent upon us to understand and work within these positions, that any one of them might be superior to our own recognitions and understandings is the very question we need to answer. Does neurological science currently explain everything to our satisfaction? More importantly, in its current form, can it? Does theology or spiritual philosophy offer any answers? Or are they – flawed as they are by assertions discontinuous with our accepted consensus reality - unlikely to be real answers at all and more likely to be just panaceas for our underlying uncertainty?

Whilst it is true that many experiences suggest that all is not quite right with our “Monday morning” view of the world, by accepting the answers of religion, spiritualism or so called “new age” metaphysics we merely leap into a box canyon of belief where science is replaced by superstition and primitive thinking. And while we certainly cannot ban unusual experiences from any inquiry into the nature of consciousness merely because they defy our preconceived ideas upon natural law, they must be viewed carefully and the projections we make upon their seeming “otherness” carefully defined and discarded.. These experiences, which Jung also found intensely interesting, are almost always considered to pose questions and offer hints which might illuminate the metaphysical nature of consciousness, or the “impossible problem”, as Professor Chalmers puts it.

The conclusions we often reach, however, are not always as valid as first might seem to those who confront or investigate such phenomena, let alone those -  followers of Jung included -  who reify or envision the human collective unconscious as a metaphysical entity rather than understand it as a projection of those archetypal dynamics initially proposed by Jung.

The evidence of veridical or “truth telling” clairvoyant experience might overrule the notion that consciousness is limited to and by brain function alone, but it does not rule out the possibility that consciousness is fundamentally a dynamic of a purely physical universe, provided we accept the more fantastic ideas of quantum theorists. This however merely puts the problem back into its original question begging form, ie, how do qualia arise, irrespective of their point of physical origin? For instance, whilst the Penrose – Hameroff quantum model might provide a hypothetical mechanism via which consciousness might couple to the physical, it in no way provides any access to the problem posed by the existence of the experiential, nor an explanation of how qualia relate to physical states. The Penrose-Hameroff idea merely shifts the problem one step further into the micro world – in the same way the problem of the origin of sub atomic particle “charge” in physics is shifted in one theory by attributing its origin to the properties of even smaller particles, the origin of whose inferred properties being no less mysterious than that for which they were invented to explain.

The real problem here, both for the investigation of consciousness and for physics is that posed by conscious distinction itself – ie, that the objectively physical is always external to consciousness; always an object of consciousness, thus making all mechanisms we posit to explain consciousness also objects of consciousness. This is the endless circle at the bottom of all conscious logic, the fundamental subjectivity of reason, the very root of the “impossible problem”.

Argument from the Jungian Perspective
Jung's initial position was the archetypes of the collective unconscious are the "images" of the instincts, i.e., the subjective side of the instincts; on the one hand rendered as psychic "objects" to the experiencing mind and on the other understood as those autonomous psychic determinants of behavior and perception arising from the "architecture" of the species neurological structure.

If we look at the archetype as the result of the inherent architecture of an organizing principle, we can see how it can give rise to a multiplicity of form. In essence the entire physical world is derived from the mechanics of particle behavior, from the architecture of energy/matter transformation. The entire periodic table of the elements and the complex and reactive processes inherent in their chemical relationships all build from the few simple parameters or organizing principles governing the way in which energy is shaped and transformed.

Within biological organisms, basic neurological structures provide the "arch" or ruling patterns which lay beneath complex survival behavior. Jung recognized that such behavioral dynamics echoed within the psyche as instincts, predetermined patterns of psycho/physical coordination which acted sub-consciously and under all circumstances where the instinct was called by external circumstances to activate.

Where Jung becomes unclear is just how these inherent patterns of the psycho/physical system attain a reflective or "imaged" condition within the psyche and thereby become the organizing principles of the subjective psychic position. It is clear enough that they appear to do so, but unclear as to how such a condition actually might arise.

If we accept there is an inherent subjective system within the neurological "psyche" in which the requirements of the instincts are "imaged", and that these images are organized via the hierarchy of archetypal dynamics, then how could this subjective point of view have come into being, to have been - necessarily, in a purely biological context - derived only from the conditional laws of matter?

Looking more closely, however, we see that the archetypes not only govern the behavioral dynamics of consciousness, but also the apprehension of subjective images. Color, sound, smell -  sensations of all kind -  are defined not by their initiating physical nature, but by architectural principles unrelated to the physical systems from which they derive, and exist as objective products within what appears to us as a purely non-physical system of organization.

For example, color is a totally subjective phenomenon, related by the cognitive processes to data arising from an optical system capable of discriminating a range of photon energy levels. Color only arises in the subjective percept as the artifact of an internal process. This suggests a pre-existing matrix of subjective imagery must be “read” to derive it – i.e., that “color” is the result of an archetypal mediation between cognitive data and a matrix of innate yet objective data.

This same innate relevance applies to all sensory imagery – sound, taste, smell, etc, and it would appear that the biological mechanisms partake of this matrix to the extent only that they are capable of discrimination. That is – color perception is not created by a chromatically discriminative optical system, but that when chromatic data is available to the cognitive processes it can be referenced against an innate archetypal matrix, allowing the perception of color within the experiential visual process.

From this it follows that key perceptive data such as color, tone, smell, taste are absolute factors continuous with an objective psychic factor not reducible to the mechanics of a biological nervous function merely “informed” by learning data.

This leads to the conclusion that there must be a co-related subjective position inherent in all seemingly purely objective states. That there is an "inside" and an "outside" to all things, that the subjective position is not something which "arises" with biological awareness, but is an inherent condition, the "other side" of "isness" which cannot be seen as separate from and is conversely always the complement of "objective" matter.

When we recognize this, we can see that for "life" to arise, the conditions of both objective and subjective organization must be met before any coordinated system of survival, self replication and evolution can occur.

This pondering of the nature of the archetypes leads us to the difficult realization that either the duality inherent in our logical processes cannot lead us beneath its own nature to any appreciation of the true unity of being, or, that within this particular universe, the duality of subject and object is in fact the rational operator; that energetic organizational principles and their inherent subjective images are the twin "co-operators" and co-creators of sentient existence.
 
Here we might make a metaphysical hypothesis: that “psyche” is not only an objective function (as suggested in my paper on relativity), but also that this objective function is no mere empty category, but is “informed”, i.e. with the absolute images from which percepts are built. This in turn suggests that it is a point of connection within and to a pleromic cosmos in which all absolute data are manifest, both that of the apparently objective and also of the apparently subjective – i.e. that qualia are in fact entities within an opposing “subjective” universe which is nothing other than the innate or hidden side of that particular “objective” or “material” universe defined by the properties of our organs of perception.

At this point one can see how Jung’s and Pauli’s idea of the two opposing cones meeting at a central mediating point reflects not only the above argument, but also the impassable limit of our conscious logic, because this point where matter and psyche meet seems ever to remain both above and behind conscious awareness; an ineffable mediating entity of experiential being. Thus this unconscious root of awareness remains projected as the creator of the experiential cosmos, as an ineffable unity ever inferring itself beneath our irrevocably subjective conscious distinctions, and whether posited as the unifying principle of the individual psyche, or that of the cosmos itself, it seems this primal archetype cannot be rooted out of our metaphysics.

To the logical, scientific mind, this is hardly a satisfactory position, the ambiguity at this point so great that we either lapse into silence or fall back, either to the never ending quest for a rational, materialistic answer or the ace up the sleeve certainty of some spiritualist position – both of which remain collectively entrenched, unsatisfactory and ever at odds, not only with each other but also with much of the experiential reality they each claim to illuminate.

Is there a third position – a transcendent function we might access here? Is the limit of our reasoning ability reached once we exhaust all possible avenues of investigation within our current notions of the world around us? Or is this merely the result of our scientific subjectivity – the result of our blind pursuit of a materialistic answer to everything?

It is here that we need not only to review those paradoxes inherent in our current vision of the cosmos, but also those otherwise inexplicable and apparently veridical subjective experiences and recognize that these offer, at the very least, a path beyond the apparent limits of our thinking. To understand this, however, requires a complete reassessment of physics and biology from a point of view which sees consciousness as an objective co-creator of reality rather than a fortuitous after effect of physical law and biological development.

In a further essay I intend to define the argument from first principles and then consider the matter of those apparently metaphysical dynamics which predispose us to believe – usually quite without foundation – that consciousness implicates a entity separate and distinct from the physical. In this essay I hope to make clear that such distinctions are the product of a subjective viewpoint whose explanation leads to the only path beyond the “impossible problem”.

Extract.

[If we speculate a pleromic universe, then it can only be one thing: there can be no part of it which is “other”. Such a universe has no attributes, and while it can be said that it is everything, it is also nothing at all; that while it is infinite in extent, it is also a single point: that while it is infinite light, it is also utter darkness.

Now these are the reflections of conscious logic, ie, without consciousness to distinguish states conditional upon its nature and perceptive attributes we arrive at a vision of the universe which might be said to be the conditional vision of primal consciousness. Thus our vision represents a limit also: that every statement we can make about the universe is a product of this primal duality of subject and object. If we allow this however, accepting its a-priori structuring of our imagery and allow further thinking as a kind of conceit which might illuminate at least something we have overlooked, we can suggest that it is therefore axiomatic that any part of a pleromic universe must share its absolute nature, ie, that it both exists and does not exist, at the same time: that any specific or conditional part of it is both itself and everything it is absolutely not at the same time – and that the one state always and ever engenders the other.]


Robert G Heyward - 2006